Saturday, December 30, 2023

The unfixed (PhD Edit)

The unfixed (PhD Edit)

1 Preface

Originally published article on 2019/06/14 and revised for an entry on academia.edu, 2023/12/30. The original website version was very short, so I also republished the new version on Blogger, 2023/12/30.

From

2010 Theodicy and Practical Theology: PhD thesis, the University of Wales, Trinity Saint David, Lampeter 

Saturday, September 19, 2020: PhD Full Version PDF: Theodicy and Practical Theology 2010, Wales TSD

The unlimited and unfixed. Blackburn (1996: 193). God is considered infinite and his creation finite and therefore limited.
---

2 The Unfixed: December 30, 2023

In the Blackburn text within his entry, infinity, it defines infinity as 'The unlimited which goes beyond any fixed bound.' (193). Theologically and philosophically, I view God as unfixed, but this unfixed nature (ontological nature) would exist within logic. God is not by nature, illogical and contradictory. For example, God could not stop being God, or make another equal, infinite, eternal God.

Referencing my PhD and website work:

John Frame explains that God cannot perform logically contradictory actions, Frame (2002: 518). Erickson (1994: 277). Shedd (1874-1890)(1980: 359-360 Volume 1). God cannot make a square circle, Frame (2002: 518). Thiessen (1956: 126). God cannot commit that which is immoral and sinful, Frame (2002: 518). Thiessen (1956: 126). Weber (1955)(1981: 440). Interestingly, God cannot commit actions ‘appropriate only to finite creatures.’ Frame (2002: 520). 

God cannot logically have finite attributes. All of God's attributes and nature are infinite. In the incarnation, God the Son takes a finite human nature, as Jesus Christ, while remaining the eternal, infinite God. But the infinite and finite natures do not mix. God the Son, as infinite, within the Trinity, did (does) take a finite, human nature in the incarnation. Correctly, and classically, the natures do not mix. Jesus Christ is both finite man and infinite God. There is an aspect of mystery in the incarnation, but the Triune nature of God which is infinite and eternal is not altered by Christ taking on additional finite human nature. According to the Pocket Dictionary, the hypostatic union is the theological term which describes the bringing together of the divine and human natures of Jesus Christ is one person. (62). God the Son, Jesus Christ, being both fully human and fully divine. (62). Hypostasis (ὑπόστασις) from the Greek in this context, is the essential nature and essence of a person/entity.

Jesus Christ remains fully, infinitely, divine and fully, finitely, human, forever as the King that will one day return to fully culminate the Kingdom of God:

Acts 1: 9-11 

New American Standard Bible: NASB 

9 And after He had said these things, He was lifted up while they were watching, and a cloud took Him up, out of their sight. 10 And as they were gazing intently into the sky while He was going, then behold, two men in white clothing stood beside them, 11 and they said, “Men of Galilee, why do you stand looking into the sky? This Jesus, who has been taken up from you into heaven, will come in the same way as you have watched Him go into heaven.”


3 Symbolic Logic

LANGER, SUSANNE K (1953)(1967) An Introduction to Symbolic Logic, Dover Publications, New York. 

Langer: Key symbols 

≡df = Equivalence by definition 
: = Equal (s) 
ε = Epsilon and means is 
⊃ = Is the same as
⊨ is Entails 
˜ = Not 
∃ = There exists 
∃! = There exists 
∴ = Therefore 
. = Therefore 
< = Is included 
v = a logical inclusive disjunction (disjunction is the relationship between two distinct alternatives)
x = variable 
. = Conjunction meaning And 
0 = Null class 
cls = Class 
int = Interpretation

My philosophical example based on reviewing the Langer text: The infinite class (God) is simply infinite, nothing can be multiplied or added to that class. The finite class is simply finite, nothing can be multiplied or added to that class.   

i = infinite
f = finite 

i ˜ ⊃ f 

The infinite is not the same as the finite. 

i ˜ ⊨ f 

The infinite does not entail the finite. 

And I add: 

i . ˜ f 

The infinite is therefore, not the finite. 

i : ˜ f 

The infinite equals not, the finite. 

(∃! i) + (∃! f) ˜ :

There exists the infinite, plus there exists the finite, they are not equal.

BLACKBURN, SIMON (1996) Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

CONWAY DAVID A. AND RONALD MUNSON (1997) The Elements of Reasoning, Wadsworth Publishing Company, New York. 

ERICKSON, MILLARD (1994) Christian Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Book House. 

ERICKSON, MILLARD (2003) What Does God Know and When Does He Know It?, Grand Rapids, Zondervan.

FRAME, JOHN M. (1999) ‘The Bible on the Problem of Evil: Insights from Romans 3:1-8,21-26; 5:1-5; 8:28-39’, IIIM Magazine Online, Volume 1, Number 33, October 11 to October 17, Fern Park, Florida, Third Millennium. 

FRAME, JOHN M. (2002) The Doctrine of God, P and R Publishing, Phillipsburg, New Jersey.

GRENZ, STANLEY J., DAVID GURETZKI and CHERITH FEE NORDLING (1999) Pocket Dictionary of Theological Terms, Downers Grove, Ill., InterVarsity Press. 

LANGER, SUSANNE K (1953)(1967) An Introduction to Symbolic Logic, Dover Publications, New York. 

PHILLIPS, D.Z. (1981) Encountering Evil, Stephen T. Davis (ed.), Atlanta, John Knox Press.

PHILLIPS, D.Z. (2005) The Problem of Evil and the Problem of God, Fortress Press, Minneapolis.

PIRIE, MADSEN (2006)(2015) How To Win Every Argument, Bloomsbury, London.
 
SHEDD, WILLIAM G.T. (1874-1890)(1980) Dogmatic Theology, Volume 1, Nashville, Thomas Nelson Publishers. 

SHEDD, WILLIAM G.T. (1874-1890)(1980) Dogmatic Theology, Volume 2, Nashville, Thomas Nelson Publishers. 

THIESSEN, HENRY C. (1956) Introductory Lectures in Systematic Theology, Grand Rapids, Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. 

WEBER, OTTO (1955)(1981) Foundations of Dogmatics, Volumes 1 and 2, Translated and annotated by Darrell L. Guder, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

Sunday, November 26, 2023

The Orthodox Study Bible: Mystery

The Orthodox Study Bible: Mystery

Preface

A September 18, 2020 article revised with significant additions on November 26, 2023, in order to place a version of this article on academia.edu.

The Orthodox Study Bible, New Testament and Psalms, (1993) Saint Athanasius Orthodox Academy, Thomas Nelson Publishers, Nashville, Tennessee.

I continue from my Reformed Christian tradition to use this fine academic source for review:

Mystery

Glossary: Reverend John W. Morris, Ph.D.

Cited

'Mystery' (803)

'The ways of God, especially God's plan for salvation, which cannot be known with the rational, finite, human mind, but can be experienced only by the revelation of God.' (803).  It is also noted that the Orthodox Church views mystery as an aspect of the sacraments. (803). 

Verses I have noted from the Orthodoxy text:

Mark 4:11 

New American Standard Bible (NASB) 

11 And He was saying to them, “To you has been given the mystery of the kingdom of God, but those who are outside get everything in parables,...

1 Corinthians 2:7 

New American Standard Bible (NASB) 

7 but we speak God’s wisdom in a mystery, the hidden wisdom which God predestined before the ages to our glory;... 

Ephesians 5:32 

New American Standard Bible (NASB) 

32 This mystery is great; but I am speaking with reference to Christ and the church. 
---

Mysterious examples

When I looked up the three verses cited within the Mystery entry, I was expecting at least one example to be an attempt at a direct reference to the sacraments, as support for Orthodox theology in regards to sacraments and mystery. But in my humble opinion, none of the verses connect directly to the sacraments.

In agreement with the entry, the first two verses, at least, do connect to salvation and in my words, the mystery of the Kingdom of God. Mark 4:11 is within the labeled section Why Parables? (92) and the mystery of the Kingdom of God. The 1 Corinthians 2:7 section is labeled as Understanding Unity: Wisdom of the Spirit (379), and the mystery of the workings of God the Holy Spirit. According to the text's heading, the third example, Ephesians 5: 32 in within The Mystery of Marriage (451) section.


Cited 

μυστήριον (root word)

Part of Speech neuter noun 

Root Word (Etymology) From a derivative of muo (to shut the mouth) 

Cited 

In classical Greek a hidden thing, secret, mystery

Verses and Greek inflections:

Mark 4: 11 μυστήριον Noun: Accusative Singular Neuter

1 Corinthians 2: 7 μυστηρίῳ Noun: Parsing: Dative Singular Neuter

Ephesians 5: 32 μυστήριον Noun: Nominative Singular Neuter

According to Greek scholar, Bauer from pages 530-531:

Cited

'μυστήριον (ου το)' (530)

Defined as 'secret, secret rite, secret teaching, mystery'. (530). In Mark 4: 11 with μυστήριον, same as the root word. Bauer writes that is the gospels this term is only found in one context 'where Jesus says to the disciples who have asked for an explanation of the parables (s)'. (530). Bauer explains that there are parallels in the synoptics with Matthew 13: 11 and Luke 8: 10. (530).


Cited

Matthew 13: 11: μυστήρια from the root μυστήριον (mystērion)

Luke 8: 10: μυστήρια from the root μυστήριον (mystērion)

The Bauer text states that the Pauline version of μυστήριον occurs in '21 places' (530) and is defined as 'A secret or mystery, too profound for human ingenuity...'. (530). The mystery of the gospel and Christ, as the 'secret of Christ 4: 3 (Colossians, my add) is proclaimed' (530). This connects to also Romans 16: 25 and 1 Corinthians 2 (530). Bauer notes with 2:7 'secretly, so that no unauthorized person would learn of it'. (531). With Ephesians 5: 32 where 'A unique great mystery is revealed'. (530).
---

Mysterious theology

Appealing to mystery, may occur theologically because of lack of significant cumulative evidences. I can admit that appealing to mystery is often an intellectual quote 'cop-out', as pointed out to me by Dr. William Kay, Wales, my MPhil, United Kingdom, academic tutor. But, I am not stating therefore that it is always error to state 'I do not know'. Not knowing is an aspect of being finite (lacking omniscience) and sinful (although believers are justified, sanctified and eventually resurrected through the applied atoning and resurrection work of Jesus Christ, Romans, 1-2 Corinthians, Galatians, Hebrews), in contrast to God's infinite and holy nature. Appealing to mystery and that which is secret is also an aspect of living within a reasonable, rational, Christian faith and philosophy.

BAUER, WALTER. (1979) A Greek-English Lexicon of the New Testament, Translated by Eric H. Wahlstrom, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press. 

CAIRD, GEORGE B. (1977) Paul's Letters from Prison Paperback, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

COAD, F. ROY (1986) ‘Galatians’, in F.F. Bruce (gen.ed.), The International Bible Commentary, Grand Rapids, Marshall Pickering/ Zondervan.

COURSON, JON (2005) Application Commentary, Thomas Nelson, Nashville. 

DUNNETT, WALTER M. (2001) Exploring The New Testament, Wheaton, Crossway Book

ELWELL, WALTER AND YARBROUGH, ROBERT W., Third Edition (2013) Encountering The New Testament, Grand Rapids, Baker Academic.

FEE, GORDON D. (1987) The First Epistle To The Corinthians, Grand Rapids, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. 

FOULKES, FRANCIS (1989) Ephesians, Grand Rapids, Inter-Varsity Press. 

GUNDRY, ROBERT (1981) A Survey of the New Testament, Grand Rapids, Zondervan. 

HARPUR, GEORGE (1986) Ephesians in The International Bible Commentary, Grand Rapids, Zondervan. 

HUGHES, PHILIP, EDGCUMBE (1990) A Commentary On The Epistle To The Hebrews, Grand Rapids, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

MARSH, PAUL, W. (1986) ‘1 Corinthians’, in F.F. Bruce, (ed.), The International Bible Commentary, Grand Rapids, Marshall Pickering/Zondervan.

MARSHALL, ALFRED (1975)(1996) The Interlinear KJV-NIV, Grand Rapids, Zondervan.

SHORT, STEPHEN S. (1986) ‘Mark’, in F.F. Bruce (ed.), The International Bible Commentary, Grand Rapids, Zondervan. 

STRONG, J. (1890)(1986) Strong's Exhaustive Concordance of the Bible, Pickering, Ontario, Welch Publishing Company.

The Orthodox Study Bible, New Testament and Psalms (1993) Saint Athanasius Orthodox Academy, Thomas Nelson Publishers, Nashville, Tennessee.

Monday, September 04, 2023

God cannot move a parked car

Parked in a traffic jam: Downtown Vancouver, June 2017

God cannot move a parked car

Preface

Originally a Sunday, June 18, 2017 article, significantly updated on Monday, September 4, 2023 for an entry on academia.edu.

Logic

God cannot move a parked car

Note, that it is not illogical for God to move a parked car, so according to God's omnipotence, God can logically move a parked car. But God's omnipotence is not the primary topic within this article. However...

God's omnipotence = God can move a parked car (equals)

God's omnipotence : God can move a parked car (equals)

God's omnipotence ⊨ God can move a parked car (entails)

God's is omnipotent ∴ God can move a parked car (therefore)

Incompatibilism

God cannot move a parked car

I have heard and read this statement and like within the evangelical church. It is often in the context of salvation, dating and marriage and seeking employment.

This statement assumes incompatibilism. Libertarian free will is usually viewed as a form of indeterminism. The concept in libertarian free will is that a person is able to perform another action in the place of one that has been committed. This action cannot be predetermined by any circumstance or desire. There can be no antecedent (prior) conditions or laws that will determine that an action is committed or not committed. Feinberg (1994: 64). With this view, freedom is incompatible with contingently sufficient nonsubsequent conditions of an action. The contingently sufficient nonsubsequent actions would be God making people in such a way that they only freely did one thing or another. Feinberg (1994: 60).

Philosopher Tim Mawson reasons that incompatibilism, which again, is also known as libertarianism or libertarian free will, in regard to human free will, believes that true human free will must be uncaused by preceding states. Mawson (1999: 324). In other words, no external force must cause a legitimate and truly free act of the human will. Within incompatibilist theory, a human action would never truly be free because God or an another external force (non-deistic view) would have willed and determined it, before being simultaneously willed to a given person. Mawson (1999: 324). 

David M. Ciocchi describes the incompatibilist idea as being God can determine that an agent commit action x, but he cannot determine that an agent commit action x freely. Ciocchi (2002: 46). The theory is that significantly free human will and actions cannot be caused by an external force. This external force would include a first cause. This external force would include God. 

Norman Geisler mentions a form of incompatibilism which he, calls self-determinism. Moral choices are not caused or uncaused by another being, but are self-caused. Incompatibilists, therefore, do not deny there are outside forces that influence significantly free human actions; however, they do not accept any notion that a free act can be caused in a determined sense by one being upon another and remain a significantly free act. An act cannot be determined or simultaneously determined and remain truly free within incompatibilism. Geisler (1986: 75). 

Moral Responsibility

Feinberg importantly writes that just as the incompatibilist does not claim that all actions are significantly free, the compatibilist also does not attach significant freedom to all acts. Feinberg (2001: 637). I reason, for example, God as primary cause, and in some cases, other secondary causes, can force or coerce human actions. But when actions are committed by a human being without significant freedom, there is not moral responsibility. For example, a person being forced or coerced to commit crimes under mind control, may not have significant moral responsibly for thoughts and actions. I state may not because in my finitude, I leave ultimate judgement of persons, post-mortem, up to God (Revelation 20).

Hard determinism 

Within hard determinism, God (theistic model) would be the only cause of human thoughts and actions, while within soft determinism/compatibilism, God would be the primary cause of human thoughts and actions and persons the secondary cause. Stace (1952)(1976: 30). 

(A non-theistic hard determinism could state as examples, fate, chance or the unknown as a possible first cause)

Louis P. Pojman explains the difference between determinism, which is also known as hard determinism, and compatibilism, which is also known as soft determinism. Pojman (1996: 596). Within determinism or hard determinism, God (or an external force) causes an act and no created being is responsible for his or her moral actions, while for compatibilism or soft determinism, although God causes actions, created beings are responsible where they act voluntarily. Pojman (1996: 596). In other words, hard determinism holds that every event is caused and no one is responsible for actions, whereas soft determinism holds that rational creatures can be held responsible for determined actions as long as they are done voluntarily and without force or coercion. Pojman (1996: 586).

Simon Blackburn comments that this is the doctrine that human action has no influence on events. Blackburn (1996: 137). Blackburn gives the opinion that fatalism is wrongly confused with determinism, which by itself carries no implications that human actions have no effect. Blackburn (1996: 137). Tomis Kapitan notes that determinism is usually understood as meaning that whatever occurs is determined by antecedent (preceding cause) conditions. Kapitan (1999: 281). 

Soft determinism/Compatibilism

Compatibilism, like incompatibilism, holds to free will but in a limited form. Pojman (1996: 596). It is also possible for angelic and fallen angelic beings to be secondary causes, significantly influencing human thought and action. Feinberg describes compatibilism as stating certain nonconstraining conditions could strongly influence actions in conjunction with human free will performing these actions. Feinberg explains that with this viewpoint, there will be no contradiction in stating God would create human beings who were significantly free, unconstrained, and yet committed actions that God willed. Feinberg (2001: 637). Within compatibilism, human beings can be simultaneously influenced to commit significantly free thoughts and actions, within incompatibilism, they cannot. These are classic definitions from my British theses work. Assuredly there are definitions and views that vary slightly.

P.S. Greenspan writes that compatibilism holds to free will and determinism being compatible. Greenspan (1998: 1). Feinberg explains that compatibilism does not allow for coercion or force, but holds that God, or some outside force, can simultaneously determine with the use of persuasion, that an action will or will not take place. Feinberg (1986: 24).

W.T. Stace (1952)(1976) explains that moral responsibility is consistent with determinism in the context of soft determinism and requires it. Stace (1952)(1976: 29). If human actions are uncaused then reward or punishment would be unjustified. Stace (1952)(1976: 29). Stace reasons that there must be at least some human cause within human actions to make them morally responsible acts. Stace (1952)(1976: 30).

It could be stated that human secondary causes, through a theoretical chain of human nature, human will and human choice, embrace what has been caused and chosen by God, the first and primary cause, directly or indirectly. The human being could also be influenced by other secondary causes, such as other persons and angelic beings, for example.

Limited free will

Based on my MPhil/PhD research and online research, my use of the term is definitively, compatibilistic. This is not the ability to choose otherwise, as in middle knowledge and versions of libertarian free will. In my compatibilistic model, at least, through a theoretical, non-exhaustive chain of human nature, human will and human choice, a person embraces as secondary cause, what was caused, willed and allowed by the primary cause. This in regard to human conscious thoughts, will, choices, acts and actions. This first cause would be God in a biblical view. During my British studies I looked for the term limited free will in texts and online and did not see it. I/we have significant moral responsibility in my/our conscious, thoughts, will, choices, acts and actions, that are not significantly forced or coerced.

God cannot move a parked car

From an incompatibilistic view, in a sense, God cannot move a parked car. A person will not be saved, date or marry, or be seeking employment, without deciding to do so autonomously, without being simultaneously influenced by God or another force, to do so. If God did so, this would be hard determinism.

From my compatibilistic view, even if God could be stated to merely allow a person to have thought leading to action, by allowing thought and action, God is causing and willing these things to occur. This is because, God, unlike any other entity is infinite, and omnipotent. God cannot, not be involved in anything.

If a person appears to be a parked car, it is because God has caused and willed it and the person has embraced the position, in thought and action as a secondary cause.

God can cause and will a car to stay parked, or God can cause and will a car to move. In either scenario, for significant moral accountability to exist within limited free will, the human being embraces what God has willed. God could force or coerce a car to stay parked or move, but then there is no moral, human, accountability.

Some would argue God can force or coerce thoughts and actions that human beings embrace. If this would be accepted, it is a different concept of embracing. In a related way, a lion can embrace killing its prey, in a sense, but I would not coin this as embracing within limited free will. A lion does not philosophize of theologize on the concept. It kills its prey by nature within what is a rationality that cannot know God, nor be morally responsible to God. A very limited rationality even in comparison to human, angelic and demonic, rational limitations. This would be hard determinism within the animal kingdom.

From a human perspective, we are to pray that God's will be done, as in the Lord's Prayer, Matthew 6, Luke 11. We should ask for things according to God's will, from I John 5, realizing God causes and wills all things in the life of the Christian, Ephesians 1-2, Romans 8-9. God causing all things to work together for good to those who love God, to those who are called according to His purpose.

The Christian should pray to be an obedient secondary cause in thought and action via a nature enlightened by the Holy Spirit through the salvific work of God through Jesus Christ.

Therefore, the title statement is false, but even so, pondering on the concepts involved, the Christian should seek to be obedient in all things.

AUGUSTINE (388-395)(1964) On Free Choice of the Will, Translated by Anna S.Benjamin and L.H. Hackstaff, Upper Saddle River, N.J., Prentice Hall. 

AUGUSTINE (398-399)(1992) Confessions, Translated by Henry Chadwick, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

AUGUSTINE (400-416)(1987)(2004) On the Trinity, Translated by Reverend Arthur West Haddan, in Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, Series One, Volume 3, Denver, The Catholic Encyclopedia. 

AUGUSTINE (421)(1998) Enchiridion, Translated by J.F. Shaw, Denver, The Catholic Encyclopedia. 

AUGUSTINE (426)(1958) The City of God, Translated by Gerald G. Walsh, Garden City, New York, Image Books. 

AUGUSTINE (427)(1997) On Christian Doctrine, Translated by D.W. Robertson Jr., Upper Saddle River, N.J., Prentice Hall. 

AUGUSTINE (427b)(1997) On Christian Teaching, Translated by R.P.H. Green, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

BLACKBURN, SIMON (1996) Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

BLACKBURN, SIMON (1996) ‘Fatalism’, in Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy,. Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

BLACKBURN, S. (1996) ‘Reductio ad Absurdum’, Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

BRUCE, F.F. (1987) Romans, Grand Rapids, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

CALVIN, JOHN (1539)(1998) The Institutes of the Christian Religion, Book IV, Translated by Henry Beveridge, Grand Rapids, The Christian Classic Ethereal Library, Wheaton College. http://www.ccel.org/ccel/calvin/institutes.html 

CALVIN, JOHN (1540)(1973) Romans and Thessalonians, Translated by Ross Mackenzie, Grand Rapids, Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. 

CALVIN, JOHN (1543)(1996) The Bondage and Liberation of the Will, Translated by G.I. Davies, Grand Rapids, Baker Book House. 

CALVIN, JOHN (1550)(1978) Concerning Scandals, Translated by John W. Fraser, Grand Rapids, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. 

CALVIN, JOHN (1552)(1995) Acts, Translated by Watermark, Nottingham, Crossway Books. 

CALVIN, JOHN (1553)(1952) Job, Translated by Leroy Nixon, Grand Rapids, Baker Book House. 

CALVIN, JOHN (1554)(1965) Genesis, Translated by John King, Edinburgh, The Banner of Truth Trust. 

COURSON, JON (2005) Application Commentary, Thomas Nelson, Nashville

CIOCCHI, DAVID M. (2002) ‘The Religious Adequacy of Free-Will Theism’, in Religious Studies, Volume 38, pp. 45-61. Cambridge. 

DUNN, JAMES D.G. (1988) Romans, Dallas, Word Books.

FEINBERG, JOHN.S. (1986) Predestination and Free Will, in David Basinger and Randall Basinger (eds.), Downers Grove, Illinois, InterVarsity Press.

EDWARDS, JONATHAN (1729)(2006) Sovereignty of God, New Haven, Connecticut, Jonathan Edwards Center, Yale University. 

EDWARDS, JONATHAN (1731-1733)(2006) Law of Nature, New Haven, Connecticut, Jonathan Edwards Center, Yale University. 

EDWARDS, JONATHAN (1754)(2006) Freedom of the Will, Flower Mound, Texas. Jonathanedwards.com. http://www.jonathanedwards.com 

ERICKSON, MILLARD (1994) Christian Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Book House. 

FEINBERG, JOHN.S. (1986) Predestination and Free Will, in David Basinger and Randall Basinger (eds.), Downers Grove, Illinois, InterVarsity Press. 

FEINBERG, JOHN.S. (1994) The Many Faces of Evil, Grand Rapids, Zondervan Publishing House. 

FEINBERG, JOHN.S. (2001) No One Like Him, John S. Feinberg (gen.ed.), Wheaton, Illinois, Crossway Books.

FLEW, ANTONY, R.M. HARE, AND BASIL MITCHELL (1996) ‘The Debate on the Rationality of Religious Belief’, in L.P. Pojman (ed.), Philosophy, The Quest for Truth, New York, Wadsworth Publishing Company. 

FLEW, ANTONY AND A.MACINTRYE (1999) ‘Philosophy of Religion’, in Alan Richardson and John Bowden (eds.), A New Dictionary of Christian Theology, Kent, SCM Press Ltd. 

FOULKES, FRANCIS (1989) Ephesians, Grand Rapids, Inter-Varsity Press.

FRANCE, R.T. (1985) Matthew, Grand Rapids, IVP, Eerdmans.

GEISLER, NORMAN L. (1975) Philosophy of Religion, Grand Rapids, Zondervan Publishing House. 

GEISLER, NORMAN L. (1978) The Roots of Evil, Grand Rapids, Zondervan Publishing House. 

GEISLER, NORMAN L. (1986) Predestination and Free Will, Downers Grove, Illinois, InterVarsity Press. 

GEISLER, NORMAN L. (1996) ‘Freedom, Free Will, and Determinism’ in Walter A. Elwell (ed.), Evangelical Dictionary of Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Books. 

HARPUR, GEORGE (1986) Ephesians in The International Bible Commentary, Grand Rapids, Zondervan.

HASKER, WILLIAM (1996) ‘Middle Knowledge’, in Robert Audi (ed.), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. 

HASKER, WILLIAM (1989) God, Time, and Knowledge, Ithaca, Cornell University Press.

HASKER, WILLIAM (1993) ‘C. Robert Mesle, John Hick’s Theodicy: A Process Humanist Critique’, in Philosophy of Religion, Volume 34, Number 1, pp. 55-56. Dordrecht, Netherlands, Philosophy of Religion. 

HASKER, WILLIAM (1994) ‘Can Philosophy Defend Theology?’, in Faith and Philosophy, Volume 11, Number 2, April, pp. 272-278. Wilmore, Kentucky, Asbury College. 

HASKER, WILLIAM (2000) ‘The Problem of Evil in Process Theism and Classical Free Will Theism’, in Process Studies, Volume. 29, Number 2, Fall-Winter, pp. 194-208. Claremont, California, Religion Online. 

HASKER, WILLIAM (2003) ‘Counterfactuals and Evil’, in Philosophia Christi, Volume 5, Number 1, pp. 235-249. La Mirada, California, Biola University. 

HASKER, WILLIAM (2003) ‘Is Free-Will Theism Religiously Inadequate? A Reply to Ciocchi’, in Religious Studies, Volume 39, Number 4, December, pp. 431-440. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

HASKER, WILLIAM (2007) ‘Peter van Inwagen, The Problem of Evil’, in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, Notre Dame, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. 

HICK, JOHN (1970) Evil and The God of Love, London, The Fontana Library. 

HICK, JOHN (1978) ‘Present and Future Life’, Harvard Theological Review, Volume 71, Number 1-2, January-April, Harvard University. 

HICK, JOHN (1981) Encountering Evil, Stephen T. Davis (ed.), Atlanta, John Knox Press. 

HICK, JOHN (1993) ‘Afterword’ in GEIVETT, R. DOUGLAS (1993) Evil and the Evidence for God, Philadelphia, Temple University Press. 

HICK, JOHN (1993) The Metaphor of God Incarnate, Louisville, Kentucky, John Know Press. 

HICK, JOHN (1994) Death and Eternal Life, Louisville, Kentucky, John Knox Press. 

HICK, JOHN (1999) ‘Life after Death’, in Alan Richardson and John Bowden (eds.), A New Dictionary of Christian Theology, Kent, SCM Press.

HOCKING, DAVID (2014) The Book of Revelation, Tustin, California, HFT Publications.

KAPITAN, TOMIS (1996) ‘Free Will Problem’, in Robert Audi (ed.), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

LANGER, SUSANNE K (1953)(1967) An Introduction to Symbolic Logic, Dover Publications, New York. (Philosophy). 

MAWSON, TIM (1999) ‘The Problem of Evil and Moral Indifference’, in Religious Studies, Volume 35, pp. 323-345. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. 

MOUNCE, ROBERT H. (1990) The Book of Revelation, Grand Rapids, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

MOUNCE, ROBERT H. (1995) The New American Commentary: Romans, Nashville, Broadman & Holman Publishers. 

PIRIE, MADSEN (2006)(2015) How To Win Every Argument, Bloomsbury, London.

PLANTINGA, ALVIN C. (1977)(2002) God, Freedom, and Evil, Grand Rapids, Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. 

PLANTINGA, ALVIN C. (1982) The Nature of Necessity, Oxford, Clarendon Press. 

PLANTINGA, ALVIN C. (2000) Warranted Christian Belief, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

POJMAN, LOUIS P. (1996) Philosophy: The Quest for Truth, New York, Wadsworth Publishing Company.

PORTER, LAURENCE.E. (1986) ‘Luke’, in F.F. Bruce (gen.ed.), The International Bible Commentary, Grand Rapids, Marshall Pickering/ Zondervan.

STACE, W.T. (1952)(1976) Religion and the Modern Mind, in John R. Burr and Milton Goldinger (eds.), Philosophy and Contemporary Issues, London, Collier Macmillan Publishers. The Orthodox Study Bible, New Testament and Psalms, (1993) Saint Athanasius Orthodox Academy, Thomas Nelson Publishers, Nashville, Tennessee. 

2010 Theodicy and Practical Theology: PhD thesis, the University of Wales, Trinity Saint David, Lampeter 


2003 The Problem of Evil: Anglican and Baptist Perspectives: MPhil thesis, Bangor University


Tuesday, July 25, 2023

Baculum, Argumentum Ad III/Appeal to Force

Baculum, Argumentum Ad III/Appeal to Force 

Photo: Granville Street, 1901, Facebook

I. Preface

I have used, edited and revised, material from two directly related, previous website articles, and one other, to create a new third article for an entry on academia.edu. 



II. Baculum, Argumentum Ad/Appeal to Force 

PIRIE, MADSEN (2006)(2015) How To Win Every Argument, Bloomsbury, London. 

'When reason fails you, appeal to the rod.' (46). Pirie lists Soviet leader, Joseph Stalin as a classic adherent. (47). This fallacious approach uses force as means of persuasion as the argument would be lost without it. (46). Interestingly, the first leader of the Soviet Union also made use of this fallacy... 

III. Vladimir Lenin

Referenced from an earlier article on this website. Vladimir Lenin's views on the use of terror are referenced, which make use of this 'fallacy of force', in my humble opinion.

My article


I referenced


Cited

'From the 1 September 1918 edition of the Bolshevik newspaper, Krasnaya Gazeta:' 

'“We will turn our hearts into steel, which we will temper in the fire of suffering and the blood of fighters for freedom. We will make our hearts cruel, hard, and immovable, so that no mercy will enter them, and so that they will not quiver at the sight of a sea of enemy blood. We will let loose the floodgates of that sea. Without mercy, without sparing, we will kill our enemies in scores of hundreds. Let them be thousands; let them drown themselves in their own blood. For the blood of Lenin and Uritsky, Zinovief and Volodarski, let there be floods of the blood of the bourgeois - more blood, as much as possible.”'

'Excerpt from an interview with Felix Dzerzhinsky published in Novaia Zhizn on 14 July 1918.'

'We stand for organized terror - this should be frankly admitted. Terror is an absolute necessity during times of revolution. Our aim is to fight against the enemies of the Soviet Government and of the new order of life. We judge quickly. In most cases only a day passes between the apprehension of the criminal and his sentence. When confronted with evidence criminals in almost every case confess; and what argument can have greater weight than a criminal's own confession.”'

'Excerpts from V.I. Lenin, “The Lessons of the Moscow Uprising” (1906) Keeping in mind the failure of the 1905 revolution, Lenin argued that it was imperative for an even more ruthless application of force in the pursuit of overthrowing the Tsar’s regime.' 

'“We should have taken to arms more resolutely, energetically and aggressively; we should have explained to the masses that it was impossible to confine things to a peaceful strike and that a fearless and relentless armed fight was necessary. And now we must at last openly and publicly admit that political strikes are inadequate; we must carry on the widest agitation among the masses in favour of an armed uprising and make no attempt to obscure this question by talk about "preliminary stages", or to befog it in any way. We would be deceiving both ourselves and the people if we concealed from the masses the necessity of a desperate, bloody war of extermination, as the immediate task of the coming revolutionary action.'
---

IV. Baculum, Argumentum Ad III/Appeal to Force continued

Baculum, Argumentum Ad (appeal to the stick, appeal to force) would be a philosophical and psychological tool at times of political dictatorships, radical religious fundamentalists, radical liberals, and the corporate world, as examples. This of course includes various forms of communism, as noted.

The fallacy could be used on a parental level... 

Example:

'Kid if you do not do as I say, you will get whooped'. (A classic approach, I do not approve of)

Pirie explains. However, the threat of force does not have to be in the form of physical violence. (46). This fallacy occurs when 'unpleasant consequences are promised for failing to comply with the speaker's wishes'. (46). The author reasons that irrelevant material is brought into an argument. (46). The argument is largely abandoned and instead, forceful persuasion is used and depended on. There is a 'breakdown and subversion of reason'. (46).  

(Certainly, a totalitarian, dictatorship like the Soviet Union, subverted reason...)

V. Lander University

Philosophy, Lander University

Cited

'I. Argumentum ad Baculum (fear of force): the fallacy committed when one appeals to force or the threat of force to bring about the acceptance of a conclusion. The ad baculum derives its strength from an appeal to human timidity or fear and is a fallacy when the appeal is not logically related to the claim being made. In other words, the emotion resulting from a threat rather than a pertinent reason is used to cause agreement with the purported conclusion of the argument.

The ad baculum contains implicitly or explicitly a threat. Behind this threat is often the idea that in the end, "Might makes right." Threats, per se, however, are not fallacies because they involve behavior, not arguments.'

('Might makes right'. how Marxist! My add)

Cited

'Often the informal structure of argumentum ad baculum is as follows.

If statement p is accepted or action a is done, then logically irrelevant event x will happen. Event x is bad, dangerous, or threatening. Therefore, statement p is true or action a should be rejected.'

Cited

'II. Examples of ad baculum fallacies:

Chairman of the Board: "All those opposed to my arguments for the opening of a new department, signify by saying, ‘I resign.’

"The Department of Transportation needs to reconsider the speed limit proposals on interstate highways for the simple reason that if they do not, their departmental budget for Department of Transportation will be cut by 25%.'

End Citations

My example

Space Commander: 'All those opposed to my orders in regard to the new security measures can open up the airlock and step outside and go for a very long walk...'

VI. Logically Fallacious

Logically Fallacious

References: {apa} Jason, G. (1987). The nature of the argumentum ad baculum. Philosophia, 17(4), 491–499. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02381067 {/apa}

Cited

'argumentum ad baculum (also known as: argument to the cudgel, appeal to the stick) 

Description: When force, coercion, or even a threat of force is used in place of a reason in an attempt to justify a conclusion. 

Logical Form: If you don’t accept X as true, I will hurt you.' 

Cited

'Jordan: Dad, why do I have to spend my summer at Jesus camp? 

Dad: Because if you don’t, you will spend your entire summer in your room with nothing but your Bible! 

Explanation: Instead of a reason, dad gave Jordan a description of a punishment that would happen. 

Exception: If the force, coercion, or threat of force is not being used as a reason but as a fact or consequence, then it would not be fallacious, especially when a legitimate reason is given with the “threat”, direct or implied.'

VII. Valid arguments

This fallacy might be used by a person or entity when as Prie noted, reason fails.

The use of this fallacy could occur for several reasons but, non-exhaustively, it could be used as...

1. X provides a sound argument with a true premise (s) and a true conclusion, that is rejected by Y.

2. X provides a less than a sound argument, that is rejected by Y.

X then resorts to the use of fallacy under review.
---

A valid deductive argument can have 

False premises and a true conclusion (FT)

False premises and a false conclusion (FF)

True premises and a true conclusion (TT)

However

True premises and a false conclusion (TF) is invalid. Valid arguments with all true premises are called sound arguments. The conclusion also being true.

BLACKBURN, SIMON (1996) Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

CONWAY DAVID A. AND RONALD MUNSON (1997) The Elements of Reasoning, Wadsworth Publishing Company, New York. 

LANDER UNIVERSITY, PHILSOPHY (1997-2020) Argumentum ad Baculum https://philosophy.lander.edu/logic/force.html
Lander University.

LANGER, SUSANNE K (1953)(1967) An Introduction to Symbolic Logic, Dover Publications, New York. 

LOGICALLY FALLACIOUS: References: {apa} Jason, G. (1987), The nature of the argumentum ad baculum. Philosophia, 17(4), 491–499. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02381067 {/apa}

PIRIE, MADSEN (2006)(2015) How To Win Every Argument, Bloomsbury, London.

WORLD FUTURE FUND 
http://www.worldfuturefund.org 

Monday, July 03, 2023

The Tin Man v The Straw Man

Wikipedia: Original novel

The Tin Man v The Straw Man (Ethical Superiority & Mispresenting an Opponent's Position, fallacies)

Preface

The main source for this article is...

PIRIE, MADSEN (2006)(2015) How To Win Every Argument, Bloomsbury, London.

I reviewed this Pirie text, entry by entry, over roughly a couple of years, online. As I am editing my website articles for entries on academia.edu, I noticed that within the Pirie text, the Straw Man entry referenced the Tim Man entry. This Canadian holiday weekend, I therefore decided to create a new website article as my template for the academia.edu entry with a review of the two fallacies combined.

The Tin Man/Ethical Superiority fallacy

Pirie:

"It is not a fallacy to be ethically superior to your opponent. It is fallacy to assume you are without supporting evidence. And the evidence must be more compelling than the fact that your opponent disagrees with you.' (92).

With my first employment post-Secondary school, a mentor in the insurance field, taught me to never assume, because it makes an:

ass/u/me

I have taken this life lesson and applied it to my academic work. This is similar to my concept of not guessing in academia, as much as possible. 

Back to Pirie:

One party assumes to be ethical with a position and therefore the other party with a contrary position is assumed unethical. (92). This is also transferred to related morality. But a different worldview or different opinion on a subject, does not necessarily make either position ethical or unethical. Pire reasons this has also been called the 'Tin Man' fallacy as in the Tin Man, from the Wizard of Oz (1939) has no heart. (93). 

This is opposed to the 'Straw Man' fallacy. (93). The Straw Man fallacy misrepresents an opponent's position, and then knocks that misrepresented position down. (193). Straw Man attacks can be connected to personal (ad hominem) attacks, as in producing fictional intellectual attacks and as well, personal attacks versus an opponent.

The fallacious implementation of Tin Man/Ethical Superiority approach is easy to imagine. The Christian accuses someone of a contrary worldview and that same worldview of being unethical and immoral. The person of a non-Christian worldview condemns the Christian and biblical and gospel views as being unethical and immoral. However, reasonable ethical standards need to be established and then a breaking of these ethics, reasonably established for a rational critique to occur.

Not assumed. 

The Straw Man fallacy

Once again, the straw man fallacy occurs when one misrepresents an opponent's position; this is created to knock down the opponent's position. (193).

Example from my Columbia Bible College experience (Paraphrased).

Student: You do not hold to Mennonite non-resistance and pacifism.

Student: You support the maintaining of law and order through state force (Romans 13, 1 Peter 2).

Student: You support 'just war.'

Student: Therefore, you support 'preventive war', under the guise of 'just war', theory.

Undergrad Russ: No, I clearly stated that I do not support, 'preventive war' theory. Nor do I think every war defined by governments as 'just war' is always a just war.

Student; Yes, you do.

Undergrad Russ: No, I clearly do not based on what I have stated. You are twisting the terminology I have used. Further, you should not be attempting to tell me what I believe.

The student misrepresented my law and order and just war position as equating with preventive war theory. This student built a straw man.

Traditionally the straw man deliberately overstates an opponent's position. (193). This was done by my opponent at Columbia Bible College. The adversary is portrayed as the extremist. (193). As was I falsely portrayed, in my example, as I did not hold to the classic Anabaptist/Mennonite position. Therefore, I disagreed the student that using the straw man. The real position of the opponent is not adequately reasoned with when this fallacy is used. (193).

This undergrad example, in my humble opinion, is also an example of lazy intellectual reasoning, which should be avoided. If one is to engage in debate, be prepared and be open-minded. An opponent's position should be evaluated reasonably and with significant rationality.

The straw man will be frequently used in religion and philosophy debates. At a different church than I attend now, a teacher and proponent of incompatiblism stated to me that 'You do not want to be a compatibilist', as he implied that equated to a hard determinist. In other words, anyone that holds to any form of determinism is a hard determinist. This is academically and philosophically, false and a misrepresentation of my position. I explained:

Incompatibilism

There can be no antecedent (prior) conditions or laws that will determine that an action is committed or not committed. Feinberg (1994: 64). With this view, freedom is incompatible with contingently sufficient nonsubsequent conditions of an action. The contingently sufficient nonsubsequent actions would be God making people in such a way that they only freely did one thing or another. Feinberg (1994: 60).

Hard determinism v Soft determinism/Compatibilism

Within hard determinism God (theistic model) would be the only cause of human actions, while with soft determinism God would be the primary cause of human actions and persons the secondary cause.

Compatibilism, like incompatibilism, holds to free will but in a limited form. Pojman (1996: 596). Feinberg, a noted compatibilist, describes compatibilism as stating certain nonconstraining conditions could strongly influence actions in conjunction with human free will performing these actions. Feinberg (2001) explains that with this viewpoint, there will be no contradiction in stating God would create human beings who were significantly free, unconstrained, and yet committed actions that God willed. Feinberg (2001: 637).

Technically, hard determinism and soft determinism/compatibilism are not defined identically and in fact have significant differences.

BLACKBURN, SIMON (1996) Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

EDWARDS, JONATHAN (1729)(2006) Sovereignty of God, New Haven, Connecticut, Jonathan Edwards Center, Yale University. http://edwards.yale.edu/archive/documents/page?document_id=10817&search_id=&source_type=edited&pagenumber=1 

EDWARDS, JONATHAN (1731-1733)(2006) Law of Nature, New Haven, Connecticut, Jonathan Edwards Center, Yale University. 

EDWARDS, JONATHAN (1754)(2006) Freedom of the Will, Flower Mound, Texas. Jonathanedwards.com.

FEINBERG, JOHN.S. (1986) Predestination and Free Will, in David Basinger and Randall Basinger (eds.), Downers Grove, Illinois, InterVarsity Press.

FEINBERG, JOHN.S. (1994) The Many Faces of Evil, Grand Rapids, Zondervan Publishing House. 

FEINBERG, JOHN.S. (2001) No One Like Him, John S. Feinberg (gen.ed.), Wheaton, Illinois, Crossway Books.

FLEW, ANTONY, R.M. HARE, AND BASIL MITCHELL (1996) ‘The Debate on the Rationality of Religious Belief’, in L.P. Pojman (ed.), Philosophy, The Quest for Truth, New York, Wadsworth Publishing Company. 

FLEW, ANTONY AND A.MACINTRYE (1999) ‘Philosophy of Religion’, in Alan Richardson and John Bowden (eds.), A New Dictionary of Christian Theology, Kent, SCM Press Ltd.

LANGER, SUSANNE K (1953)(1967) An Introduction to Symbolic Logic, Dover Publications, New York. (Philosophy). 

MACKIE, J.L. (1955)(1996) ‘Evil and Omnipotence’, in Mind, in Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger (eds.), Philosophy of Religion, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

MACKIE, J.L. (1971)(1977)(2002) ‘Evil and Omnipotence’, in The Philosophy of Religion, in Alvin C. Plantinga, God, Freedom, and Evil, Grand Rapids. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

PIRIE, MADSEN (2006)(2015) How To Win Every Argument, Bloomsbury, London.

PLANTINGA, ALVIN C. (1977)(2002) God, Freedom, and Evil, Grand Rapids, Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. 

PLANTINGA, ALVIN C. (1982) The Nature of Necessity, Oxford, Clarendon Press.

POJMAN, LOUIS P. (1996) Philosophy: The Quest for Truth, New York, Wadsworth Publishing Company.

STACE, W.T. (1952)(1976) Religion and the Modern Mind, in John R. Burr and Milton Goldinger (eds.), Philosophy and Contemporary Issues, London, Collier Macmillan Publishers.

My mentioned previous articles 



Saturday, May 27, 2023

Sabellianism and modalism (non-exhaustive) II

Sabellianism and modalism (non-exhaustive) II

Photo: Neuschwanstein Castle, Germany, Exploring, May 2023 

Preface

A new article for an entry on academia.edu, May 27, 2023.


Monarchianism/Patripassianism

According to C. A. Blaising, monarchianism, also known as patripassianism and sabellianism refers to a mainly Western concept of the third century which attempted to defend monotheism against tritheism by denying personal distinctions between Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. Blaising (1996: 727). Blaising notes the term monarchianism was first used by Tertullian to denote those that wished to protect the monarchy of the one God from wrong theology concerning the economy of the Father, Son and Holy Spirit. Blaising (1996: 727).

Blaising noted this first (dynamic monarchianism) view had proposed monotheistic God, as in the Father in relation to Jesus a mere man who was 'endowed with the Holy Spirit'. Blaising (1996: 727). This view was supported in Rome in around 190 by Thedotus of Byzantium and then by Artemon/Theodotus. This first view was refuted by Hippolytus. Blaising (1996: 727).  Erickson notes that dynamic monarchianism seemed to deny the trinity. Erickson (1994: 334). 

Modalism

Paul of Samosata depersonalized the Logos as the inherent rationality of God, the 'homoousia' of God. Blaising (1996: 727). The substance of God. For this Paul, the Holy Spirit was not a separate being but the grace of the Father. Blaising (1996: 727). This Paul also denied the preincarnate Word of God, and his teaching was condemned at the Synod of Antioch in 268. This second view also became known as modalism. Blaising. (1996: 727). 

Sabellius was in Rome, Blaising (1996: 727), Turner (1999: 514). There is a possibility he may have been from Libya. Turner (1999: 514). He taught modalism in the third century and thus concepts developed the name Sabellianism. Turner explains sabellianism as an alternative denotation of modalism. Turner (1999: 514). Blaising states that Sabellius is often confused with Marcus of Ancyrra of the fourth century. He reasoned a divine monad named Huiopator projected itself as Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. The Father as creator and lawgiver, the Son as redeemer the Spirit as grace giver. These were three different modes revealing the same divine person. Blaising (1996: 727). 

Erickson did examine modalism in his text in regard to the trinity. There is one God, variously designated as Father, Son and Holy Spirit but they do not stand for any real distinctions, but are simply useable at different times. Erickson (1994: 334). 

An objection raised by trinitarians, and rightly so, is that the New Testament interactions between the Father and Son appear to be very real conversations and not based in modes. 

A reasonable point could be made that yes the human Jesus Christ was interacting with the divine Father in sinless perfection, but this was being done largely because in eternity, God the Son/Word had been interacting with God the Father in a similar way (John 1), prior to taking on a finite human body. The triune God, interacting in a timeless eternal state, a relationship of infinite knowledge and understanding.

ὑποστάσεως


New American Standard Bible (NASB)

Hebrews 1: 3 3 [a]And He is the radiance of His glory and the exact representation of His nature...

Marshall page 641. 

radiance  apaugasma
representation  carakthr
reality upostasewV
---

Reality = Nature

Concerning Hebrews 1, for example, it is demonstrated in the New Testament that the Father and Son are of the same substance and nature. 

The Orthodox Study Bible, New Testament and Psalms, (1993), In the Glossary, mentions Hypostasis: 

'A technical theological term for "person" or something which has an individual existence. The word is used to describe the three Persons of the Godhead: the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit.' (800). Hypostasis is also used to describe the one Person of Christ, who is both truly divine and truly human. (800).

The Orthodox Study Bible at the notes from Hebrews 1: 2-3:

ὑποστάσεως

'The express image of His person.' (513). This is in regard to God the Son's Person as being distinct from God the Father. (513).


Cited

'Hebrews 1:3 N-GFS GRK: χαρακτὴρ τῆς ὑποστάσεως αὐτοῦ φέρων NAS: and the exact representation of His nature, and upholds KJV: of his person, and INT: [the] exact expression of the substance of him upholding' 

End citation
---

From Bauer... ὑπόστασις 'substantial nature, essence, actual being, reality'. (847). In the context of Hebrews 1: 3 (ὑποστάσεως my add), the Son of God is the exact representation of God's real being. (847). In other words, God the Son, even as in a finite human body, incarnated, still represents the nature of the infinite God in bodily form. This done without changing God's infinite nature, whatsoever.

Colossians 2:9 New American Standard Bible (NASB) 

9 For in Him all the fullness of Deity dwells in bodily form. 
---

The incarnation added finite human nature to God the Son (two natures, two minds, one person), but it in no way cancels out, changes or mixes with God the Son's infinite, eternal nature.

The Holy Spirit is not the focus of this short article. But in Acts 5, and in Matthew 28: 19, the Holy Spirit can be demonstrated as divine and I would therefore deduce is of the same divine substance and nature as God the Father and God the Son. It should be noted that triune persons are not three separate natures/Gods. The persons of the trinity could also be called distinctions, but they do personally interact according to the New Testament. 

BAUER, WALTER. (1979) A Greek-English Lexicon of the New Testament, Translated by Eric H. Wahlstrom, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press. 

BLAISING, C.A. (1996) ‘Monarchianism' in Walter A. Elwell (ed.), Evangelical Dictionary of Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Books. 

BLAISING, C.A. (1996) ‘Nicea, Council of (325)’ in Walter A. Elwell (ed.), Evangelical Dictionary of Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Books. 

BOWMAN, ROBERT M. (1990) Why You Should Believe in the Trinity, Grand Rapids, Baker Book House. 

BROM, ROBERT H. (1983) The Eternal Sonship of Christ, San Diego, CIC 827. 

BROMILEY, G.W. (1996) ‘Trinity’ in Walter A. Elwell (ed.), Evangelical Dictionary of Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Books. 

BROWNING, W.R.F. (1997) Dictionary of the Bible, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 

COURSON, JON (2005) Application Commentary, Thomas Nelson, Nashville.

ERICKSON, MILLARD (1994) Christian Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Book House. 

FRANKE, JOHN R. (2005) The Character of Theology, Baker Academic, Grand Rapids.

HAWTHORNE, GERALD F. (1986) 'Hebrews', in The International Bible Commentary, Grand Rapids, Zondervan. 

HUGHES, PHILIP, EDGCUMBE (1990) A Commentary On The Epistle To The Hebrews, Grand Rapids, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. 

MARSHALL, ALFRED (1975)(1996) The Interlinear KJV-NIV, Grand Rapids, Zondervan.

SCHRECK, ALAN (1984) Catholic and Christian, Ann Arbor, Michigan, Servant Books.

STRONG, J. (1890)(1986) Strong's Exhaustive Concordance of the Bible, Burlington, Welch Publishing Company.

The Orthodox Study Bible, New Testament and Psalms (1993) Saint Athanasius Orthodox Academy,Thomas Nelson Publishers, Nashville, Tennessee. 

THIESSEN, HENRY C. (1956) Introductory Lectures in Systematic Theology, Grand Rapids, Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

TURNER, H. E. W. (1999) 'Sabellianism', in Alan Richardson and John Bowden (eds.), A New Dictionary of Christian Theology, Kent, SCM Press Limited.

Tuesday, April 25, 2023

Theodicy and Resurrection (PhD Edit) with Propaganda Posters

Theodicy and Resurrection (PhD Edit) with Propaganda Posters

Neuschwanstein Castle, Germany (trekearth)

Preface

Reworked from a May 1, 2012 posting, for an entry on both Blogger and academia.edu, April 25, 2023

Theodicy and Resurrection (PhD Edit)

The resurrection is a complex subject that is far beyond the scope of this thesis and could easily be a topic of a large work. However, the traditional Reformed, Calvinistic perspective accepts the concept of an actual physical resurrection of Christ,
[1] and the eventual physical resurrection of humanity.[2] Erickson writes that Scripture teaches the resurrection of those who believe in Christ.[3] He also reasons it is likely that unbelievers too will be raised,[4] although this concept is not as clearly explained as is the idea of the raising of those who trust in Christ.[5] Thiessen bases the traditional Christian belief in physical resurrection in the texts from both Testaments[6] and describes the resurrection bodies as both physical and spiritual in nature.[7] Whale writes that the resurrection is not to be considered an addition to the Christian faith, but is the Christian faith.[8] Theologian Robert B. Sloan (1991) reasons that for early Christians the resurrection vindicated Christ in regard to his detractors and gave his message authority.[9] Jürgen Moltmann writes that as the crucified one, the risen Christ is available for humanity.[10] Moltmann explains to some the resurrection of Christ is a counter to the abandonment of humanity of God while Christ was on the cross.[11] For certain observers Christ’s resurrection for all turns them from atheism.[12] This may be because the historical resurrection of Christ would be viewed as God actually participating in the world to remedy the problem of evil.[13] God would not only be judging the world as he did on the cross,[14] but actually bringing about resolution to the problem of evil through Christ[15] and from a human perspective this makes a belief and trust in the Biblical God reasonable and worthwhile.

Roman Catholic, Ivone Gebara in Out of the Depths within the section entitled ‘The cross mixed with resurrection’ writes that for those within modern feminist thought it is tempting to give up the cross, which includes the idea of resurrection as the supreme symbol of Christian faith.
[16] Instead of a complete abandonment of traditional resurrection, reinterpretation takes place.[17] Resurrection becomes more than historical theology[18] but is the actual lived and grasped experience within the lives of women and persons.[19] Gebara notes that one can philosophically go beyond the idea of resurrection as the event following the death of a body, which is ancient idealistic theory.[20] She deduces that the metaphorical resurrection of actual persons today in physical bodies is a more valuable concept than the traditional one of resurrection.[21] C.F. Evans (1970) explains in a similar way that the use of symbolic language to describe historical figures in the context of resurrection complicates the issue of accepting the doctrine of physical resurrection.[22] Evans’ article supports the conclusion that the traditional doctrine largely rests upon an acceptance of the New Testament data,[23] and I agree. Although I disagree with Gebara’s reinterpretation of the doctrine of resurrection,[24] since this thesis involves practical theology[25] I can readily admit that it is important to deal with the problem of evil in actual physical bodies within today’s world.[26] The social redemption discussed by Gebara desires a move towards dealing with the problem of evil in the midst of the trials of life,[27] and I can intellectually support this concept[28] even while maintaining a doctrinal acceptance of the actual physical resurrection of Christ[29] and the eventual resurrection of humanity.[30]

Clarence Darrow (1928)(1973) writes that resurrection of the body is purely a religious doctrine.[31] He reasons that few intelligent persons when faced with evidence would hold to a doctrine of resurrection.[32] He deduces that those within the New Testament era had little scientific knowledge, and therefore resurrection doctrine is a product of those with blind faith, wild dreams, hopeless hopes, and cowardly fears.[33] Darrow’s assumption[34] would more likely be correct if the Hebrew Bible and New Testament were written by persons that were clearly writing mythological literature with the primary use of metaphorical language.[35] However, as noted there are those within both conservative and liberal Christian traditions that would reason the historical writers of Scripture wrote what they saw and experienced, and therefore many of these modern scholars accept a doctrine of physical resurrection.[36] Moltmann writes that after the resurrection the risen Christ appeared to his followers in order to guarantee that the glory of God and his creation would occur in the not too distance future.[37] This is an ultimate of hope of a sovereignty theodicy.

[1] Erickson (1994: 776-779).

[2] Erickson (1994: 1194).

[3] Erickson (1994: 1194).

[4] Erickson (1994: 1194).

[5] Erickson (1994: 1200).

[6] Thiessen (1956: 491).

[7] Thiessen (1956: 491).

[8] Whale (1958: 69).

[9] Sloan (1991: 449).

[10] Moltmann (1993: 195).

[11] Moltmann (1993: 195).

[12] Moltmann (1993: 195).

[13] Others such as Darrow, Phillips, and Flew would be very skeptical of this concept. Phillips (2005: 247-275). Darrow (1928)(1973: 266-267). Flew (1983)(1996: 92). If one does not believe in the resurrection of Christ, God’s key witness to the world that he wishes to save it from the problem of evil is gone. The remedy to sin and death would be non-existent and therefore concepts of a perfected world far-fetched.

[14] Moltmann (1993: 195).

[15] Moltmann (1993: 195).

[16] Gebara (2002: 120).

[17] Gebara (2002: 121).

[18] Gebara (2002: 121).

[19] Gebara (2002: 122).

[20] Gebara (2002: 122).

[21] Gebara (2002: 122).

[22] Evans (1999: 501-503).

[23] Evans (1999: 501-503).

[24] Gebara (2002: 122).

[25] Primarily with Chapters Five and Six.

[26] Gebara (2002: 122).

[27] Gebara (2002: 124).

[28] Gebara (2002: 124).

[29] Whale (1958: 65-70). Anderson (2001: 101). Mounce (1990: 369-397).

[30] Mounce (1990: 360).

[31] Darrow (1928)(1973: 266).

[32] Darrow (1928)(1973: 266).

[33] Darrow (1928)(1973: 266-267).

[34] Darrow (1928)(1973: 266-267).

[35] This as opposed to writing historical based religious history with the use of plain literal and figurative literal language.

[36] Moltmann (1993: 160-199). Erickson (1994: 1194-1204). Excepting that there are those that reinterpret such as Gebara with her feminist views. Gebara (2002: 122-124).

[37] Moltmann (1993: 178).
---

ANDERSON, RAY S. (2001) The Shape of Practical TheologyDowners GroveIllinois, InterVarsity Press.

DARROW, CLARENCE (1928)(1973) ‘The Myth of the Soul’ in The Forum, October, in Paul Edwards and Arthur Pap (eds), A Modern Introduction To Philosophy, New York, The Free Press.


ERICKSON, MILLARD (1994) Christian Theology
Grand Rapids, Baker Book House.

FLEW, ANTONY, R.M. HARE, AND BASIL MITCHELL (1983) (1996) ‘The Debate on the Rationality of Religious Belief’, in L.P. Pojman (ed.), Philosophy, The Quest for Truth, New York, Wadsworth Publishing Company.

GEBARA, IVONE (2002) Out of the Depths, Translated by Ann Patrick Ware, Minneapolis, Fortress Press.

MOUNCE, ROBERT H. (1990) The Book of Revelation, Grand Rapids, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.


MOLTMANN, JÜRGEN (1993) The Crucified God
Minneapolis, Fortress Press.

PHILLIPS, D.Z. (2005) The Problem of Evil and the Problem of God, Fortress Press, Minneapolis.


SLOAN, ROBERT B (1991) ‘Unity in Diversity’, in David Alan Black and David S. Dockery (eds.), New Testament Criticism and Interpretation, Grand Rapids, Zondervan Publishing House.


THIESSEN, HENRY C. (1956) Introductory Lectures in Systematic Theology, Grand Rapids, Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.


WHALE, J.S. (1958) Christian Doctrine, Glasgow, 
Fontana Books
---

Propaganda Posters

Allposters.com

This features propaganda posters. I am attempting to stay with my graphic and colour themes, problem of evil and theodicy themes; I thought I would provide some more cited propaganda posters.

AllPosters

United States of America, likely World War Two

AllPosters

I deduce this is from the United Kingdom, World War Two era..

Citing

Shorpy

'Circa 1942 silkscreen poster by Louis Hirshman encouraging safe disposal of matches, showing stylized Japanese soldier standing behind a tree with a match, with the rising sun in the background. Federal Art Project / WPA War Services '

AllPosters


United Kingdom, World War Two. And 'Keep Calm' is popular today on many blogs.

AllPosters

The Soviet Union

'The Advance of Socialism: a Crowd Tramples a Bourgeois' by Anton Hansen

It was ugly then as it is now.