
Henry C.Thiessen (PhD Edit)
Preface
Photo, May 2025. This work from my PhD was originally published on Blogger, 20140403, revised for an entry on academia.edu, 20250726.
Henry Clarence Thiessen (1884-1947)
I bought Thiessen’s 1956 theology textbook used while an undergrad at Columbia Bible College. I find his work useful even though he takes an incompatibilist position in contrast to my compatibilist one.
A Biblical Studies Professor at Columbia Bible College was quite dismissive of Thiessen stating, paraphrased that ‘Thiessen was a dispensationalist’. One of my local unofficial Doctoral, PhD advisers stated, Thiessen was basically a compiler of information and not very original. Also dismissive. Based on this limited work I shall let you form your own opinion.
Naturalism
Wheaton professor, Henry Clarence Thiessen (1956) explains that since naturalism holds that nature is the whole of reality, everything that occurs is due to the laws of nature.[1] He comments Scripture recognizes the existence of the laws of nature, but it is reasoned they do not operate independently of God.[2] God concurs with the laws he has established,[3] and Thiessen reasons that miracles and revelation can occur when God operates outside of laws he established.[4]
Incompatibilism
Thiessen writes God knows the future,[5] and that is defined as foreknowledge.[6] He also points out that God’s prescience does not mean God predetermined these actions.[7] Thiessen is noting that human acts within God’s prescient foreknowledge are still significantly free.[8]
Leibniz has a different view than Thiessen,[9] that is deterministic and reasons that foreknowledge has to do with God’s determined will and is not dependent on free human actions.[10] This predetermination should not be understood as by necessity eliminating all human choice.[11] Erickson takes a reasonable compatibilistic position and writes God with foreknowledge sees many possibilities and influences that will be present, and then acts accordingly to his will.[12]
Thiessen from an incompatibilist position writes that God does not want to create automaton type beings with no choice in whether or not they would glorify God.[13] For Thiessen, humanity can only truly glorify God by choosing to do so while still having the opportunity to choose not to glorify God in disobedience.[14] This concept appears on the surface to be primarily in line with noted incompatibilism and free will approaches almost verbatim.[15]
On Scripture
Thiessen dismisses the idea of a dictation theory of Scriptural inspiration, as the writers of Scripture were not persons that merely had divine information dictated to them.[16] The writers of Scripture were not ‘mere secretaries’ that wrote words dictated to them by the Holy Spirit.[17] It can therefore be reasoned it is not the Holy Spirit’s grammar being used.[18] The distinctive style of Biblical writers based on the study of original languages makes the dictation theory quite unlikely.[19] The concept of Biblical inspiration, with the Holy Spirit serving as guidance for the Biblical writer, seems both orthodox and reasonable.[20] The Biblical authors had full use of their intellect and used their own grammar, but were guided to write God’s word without error and omission.[21] The Holy Spirit guided the thoughts of Biblical writers.[22] Shedd names this basic theory of Biblical inspiration as ‘plenary inspiration’ meaning writers were moved by the Holy Spirit in respect to thought and language and were kept from error.[23]
Modern theology needs to correctly discern what the Spirit is stating through the Bible and this needs to be done through proper research techniques.
ERICKSON, MILLARD (1994) Christian Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Book House.
ERICKSON, MILLARD (2003) What Does God Know and When Does He Know It? Grand Rapids, Zondervan.
GEISLER, NORMAN L. (1975) Philosophy of Religion, Grand Rapids, Zondervan Publishing House.
GEISLER, NORMAN L. (1978) The Roots of Evil, Grand Rapids, Zondervan Publishing House.
GEISLER, NORMAN L. (1986) Predestination and Free Will, Downers Grove, Illinois, InterVarsity Press.
GEISLER, NORMAN L. (1996) ‘Freedom, Free Will, and Determinism’, in Walter A. Elwell (ed.), Evangelical Dictionary of Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Books.
GEISLER, NORMAN, L (1999) ‘The Problem of Evil’, in Baker Encyclopedia of Apologetics, Grand Rapids, Baker Books.
LEIBNIZ, G.W. (1710)(1998) Theodicy, Translated by E.M. Huggard Chicago, Open Court Classics.
LINDSELL, HAROLD (1976) The Battle for the Bible, Grand Rapids, Zondervan Publishing House.
PACKER, J.I. (1996) ‘Regeneration’ in Walter A. Elwell (ed.), Evangelical Dictionary of Theology, Grand Rapids, Baker Books.
PACKER, J.I. (1973) Knowing God, Downers Grove, Illinois, InterVarsity Press.
SHEDD, WILLIAM G.T. (1874-1890)(1980) Dogmatic Theology, Volume 1, Nashville, Thomas Nelson Publishers.
SHEDD, WILLIAM G.T. (1874-1890)(1980) Dogmatic Theology, Volume 2, Nashville, Thomas Nelson Publishers.
THIESSEN, HENRY C. (1956) Introductory Lectures in Systematic Theology, Grand Rapids, Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.
[1] Thiessen (1956: 186).
[2] Thiessen (1956: 186).
[3] Thiessen (1956: 186).
[4] Thiessen (1956: 186).
[5] Thiessen (1956: 125).
[6] Thiessen (1956: 125).
[7] Thiessen (1956: 126).
[8] Thiessen (1956: 126).
[9] Thiessen (1956: 126).
[10] Leibniz (1710)(1998: 147).
[11] Leibniz (1710)(1998: 147).
[12] Erickson (1994: 360).
[13] Thiessen (1956: 248).
[14] Thiessen (1956: 248).
[15] Geisler (1986: 76-77).
[16] Thiessen (1956: 106).
[17] Lindsell (1976: 32).
[18] Thiessen (1956: 106). People were not robotically inspired to write Scripture.
[19] Erickson (1994: 207).
[20] Thiessen (1956: 106). Lindsell (1976: 30).
[21] Thiessen (1956: 106). The Scripture was presented accurately via inspiration, states Erickson. Erickson (1994: 199). J.I. Packer reasons God and Christ sent the Holy Spirit to teach his people the truth and to save them from error. Packer (1973: 61).
[22] Erickson (1994: 215).
[23] Shedd (1874-1890)(1980: 72 Volume 1).
-------------------------------------------------------
20250726
Preface II
Compatibilism versus Incompatibilism has been discussed on various MPhil/PhD related articles and on my website work. Below is the MPhil/PhD link.
Saturday, September 19, 2020 PhD Full Version PDF: Theodicy and Practical Theology 2010, Wales TSD
Scripture has been discussed significantly on my website, with an increased use of New Testament Greek citations within Biblical Studies entries. For the revised version of this article, I wish to further discuss naturalism which has been less reviewed within my work overall.
Naturalism
For Thiessen, he reasoned 'naturalism holds that nature is the whole of reality...' Thiessen (1956: 186).
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Naturalism (2007-2020).
David Papineau (2020)
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy explains that 'The term “naturalism” has no very precise meaning in contemporary philosophy. Its current usage derives from debates in America in the first half of the last century.' This reads as true. 'Naturalism', when used seems to be encompassing a series of varied beliefs, rather than one distinct philosophy. There is philosophical agreement where it is reasoned, reality is based in nature and not in the supernatural.
My findings over the years with reading, listening online and with in-person discussions, have been that a person may not describe self as a naturalist, but may state he/she believes in science, as opposed to the supernatural; or a person might state they are an empiricist and do not hold to a belief in the supernatural. Such a person is making a naturalistic division philosophically from that which is supernaturalistic. But this does not in many cases mean as certain that such a person is philosophically embracing the term 'naturalism', within his/her worldview. Seems to me the term 'naturalism' is often used by evangelicals to describe the worldview of those that do not believe in the supernatural. Therefore, again, the description from Stanford that “naturalism” has no very precise meaning in contemporary philosophy, rings true and has for years for me via my research.
- Alter, T. and Pereboom, D., 2019, “Russellian Monism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/russellian-monism/>.
- Armstrong, D., 1968, A Materialist Theory of the Mind, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Baker, A., 2005, “Are there Genuine Mathematical Explanations of Physical Phenomena?”, Mind, 114: 223–38.
- Batterman, R., 2010, “On the Explanatory Role of Mathematics in Empirical Science”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61: 1–25.
- Bennett, K., 2003, “Why the Exclusion Problem Seems Intractable, and How, Just Maybe, to Tract It”, Nous, 37: 471–97.
- Bickle, J., 2013, “Multiple Realizability”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/multiple-realizability/>.
- Blackburn, S., 1993, Essays in Quasi-Realism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Boyd, R., 1988, “How to Be a Moral Realist”, in G. Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on Moral Realism, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 181–228.
- Braddon-Mitchell, D. and Nola, R. (eds.), Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Brandom, R., 2001, “Reason, Expression, and the Philosophical Enterprise”, in C. Ragland and S. Heidt (eds.), What Is Philosophy?, New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Brown, C., 2017, “A Properly Physical Russellian Physicalism”, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 24: 31–50.
- Burge, T., 1993a, “Mind-Body Causation and Explanatory Practice”, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- –––, 1993b, “Content Preservation”, Philosophical Review, 102: 457–88.
- Butterfield, J., 2011, “Less is Different: Emergence and Reduction Reconciled”, Foundations of Physics, 41(6): 1065–1135.
- Cappelen, H., 2012, Philosophy without Intuitions, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Cappelen, H., David Plunkett, D. and Burgess, A., 2019, Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Chalmers, D., 1996, The Conscious Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2012, Constructing the World, New York: Oxford University Press.
- Craig, W. and J. Moreland (eds.), 2000, Naturalism: A Critical Analysis, London: Routledge.
- Daly, C. and S. Langford, 2009, “Mathematical Explanation and Indispensability Arguments”, Philosophical Quarterly, 59: 641–658.
- Davidson, D., 1970, “Mental Events”, in L. Foster and J. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory, London: Duckworth. Reprinted in Davidson 1980.
- –––, 1980, Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- DePaul, M. and W. Ramsey (eds.), 1998, Rethinking Intuition, Lanham, Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield.
- Draper, P., 2005, “God, Science, and Naturalism”, in W. Wainwright (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Elkana, Y., 1974, The Discovery of the Conservation of Energy, London: Hutchinson.
- Enoch, D., 2011, Taking Morality Seriously, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Feigl, H., 1958, “The ‘Mental’ and the ‘Physical’”, in H. Feigl, M. Scriven and G. Maxwell (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume II, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
- Field, H., 1980, Science Without Numbers, Oxford: Blackwell.
- –––, 1989, Realism, Mathematics and Modality, Oxford: Blackwell.
- Fodor, J., 1974, “Special Sciences or: The Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis”, Synthese, 28: 97–115.
- Gibbard, A., 2003, Thinking How To Live, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- Goldman, A. 2007: “Philosophical Intuitions: Their Target, Their Source, and Their Epistemic Status”, Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74: 1–26.
- Hale, B. and C. Wright, 2003, The Reason’s Proper Study: Essays towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Hare, R., 1952, The Language of Morals, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Harman, G., 1986, “Moral Explanations of Natural Facts”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 24: 69–78.
- Hempel, C., 1969, “Reduction: Ontological and Linguistic Facets”, in S. Morgenbesser et al. (eds.), Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel, New York: St Martin’s Press.
- Honderich, T., 1982, “The Argument for Anomalous Monism”, Analysis, 42: 59–64.
- Hornsby, J., 1997, Simple-Mindedness: In Defence of Naïve Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- Jackson, F., 1982, “Epiphenomenal Qualia”, Philosophical Quarterly, 32: 127–36.
- –––, 1986, “What Mary Didn’t Know”, Journal of Philosophy, 83: 291–5.
- –––, 1993, “Armchair Metaphysics”, in J. O’Leary-Hawthorne and M. Michael (eds.), Philosophy in Mind, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- –––, 1998, From Metaphysics to Ethics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- –––, 2003, “Mind and Illusion”, in A. O’Hear (ed.), Minds and Persons, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Jenkins, C., 2008, Grounding Concepts: An Empirical Basis for Arithmetical Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2012, “A Priori Knowledge: The Conceptual Approach”, in A. Cullison (ed.), The Continuum Companion to Epistemology, London: Continuum Press.
- Joyce, R., 2015, “Moral Anti-Realism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/moral-anti-realism/>.
- Kalderon, M., 2005, Moral Fictionalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Kim, J., 1998, Mind in a Physical World, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- –––, 2003, “The American Origins of Philosophical Naturalism”, Journal of Philosophical Research, APA Centennial Volume: 83–98.
- Knobe J. and Nichols, S. (eds.), 2008, Experimental Philosophy, New York: Oxford University Press.
- –––,“Experimental Philosophy”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/experimental-philosophy/>.
- Kornblith, H., 2002, Knowledge and Its Place in Nature, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Krikorian, Y. (ed.), 1944, Naturalism and the Human Spirit, New York: Columbia University Press.
- Kroedel, T., 2015, “Dualist Mental Causation and the Exclusion Problem”, Nous, 49: 357–75.
- Leng, M., 2013, Mathematics and Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Leng, M., 2016, “Taking Morality Mathematically: Enoch’s Indispensability Argument” in U. Leibowitz and N. Sinclair, N. (eds.) Explanation in Ethics and Mathematics: Debunking and Dispensability, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 204–15.
- Lenman, J., 2014, “Moral Naturalism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/naturalism-moral/>.
- Lewis, D., 1966, “An Argument for the Identity Theory”, Journal of Philosophy, 63: 17–25.
- –––, 1970, “How to Define Theoretical Terms”, Journal of Philosophy, 67: 427–46.
- List, C. and P. Menzies, 2009, “Non-Reductive Physicalism and the Limits of the Exclusion Principle”, Journal of Philosophy, 106: 475–502.
- –––, 2010, “The Causal Autonomy of the Special Sciences”, in C. Macdonald and G. Macdonald (eds.), Emergence in Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Loewer, B., 2007, “Counterfactuals and the Second Law”, in H. Price and R. Corry (eds.), Causation, Physics, and the Constitution of Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Lowe, E.J., 2000, “Causal Closure Principles and Emergentism”, Philosophy, 75: 571–85.
- –––, 2003, “Physical Causal Closure and the Invisibility of Mental Causation”, in S. Walter and H.-D. Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation, Exeter: Imprint Academic.
- MacBride, F., 2003, “Speaking with Shadows: A Study of Neo-Logicism”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54: 103–63.
- McDowell, J., 1996, Mind and World, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- Mackie, J., 1977, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
- Maddy, P., 1990, Realism in Mathematics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Mellor D., 1995, The Facts of Causation, London: Routledge.
- Menon, T. and C. Callender, 2013, “Turn and Face the Strange … Ch-ch-changes”, in R. Batterman (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Physics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Menzies, P., 2008, “Causal Exclusion, the Determination Relation, and Contrastive Causation”, in J. Kallestrup and J. Hohwy (eds.), Being Reduced: New Essays on Reductive Explanation and Special Science Causation, Oxford: Oxford University Press
- Montero, B., 2015, “Russellian Physicalism”, in T. Alter and Y. Nagasawa (eds.), Consciousness in the Physical World: Perspectives on Russellian Monism, New York: Oxford University Press.
- Montero, B. and D. Papineau, 2005, “A Defence of the Via Negativa Argument for Physicalism”, Analysis, 65: 233–7.
- Moore, G., 1903, Principia Ethica, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Nagel, J., 2007, “Epistemic Intuitions”, Philosophy Compass, 2/6: 792–819.
- Nolan, D., 2011a, “Modal Fictionalism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/fictionalism-modal/>.
- –––, 2011b, “Modal Fictionalism and Possible World Semantics” (supplement to “Modal Fictionalism”, Winter 2011 edition), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/fictionalism-modal/supplement3.html>.
- Oppenheim, H. and P. Putnam, 1958, “Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis”, in H. Feigl, M. Scriven, and G. Maxwell (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume II, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
- Papineau, D., 2001, “The Rise of Physicalism”, in C. Gillett and B. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and its Discontents, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- –––, 2013, “Causation is Macroscopic but not Irreducible”, in S. Gibb, E. Lowe, and R. Ingthorsson (eds.), Mental Causation and Ontology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2014, “The Poverty of Conceptual Analysis”, in M. Haug (ed.), Philosophical Methodology, London: Routledge.
- –––, 2015, “The Nature of A Priori Intuitions: Analytic or Synthetic?”, in E. Fischer and J. Collins (eds.), Experimental Philosophy, Rationalism, and Naturalism, London: Routledge.
- Parfit, D., 2011, On What Matters, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Parsons, C., 1995, “Platonism and Mathematical Intuition in Kurt Gödel’s Thought”, Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 1(1): 44–74.
- Plantinga, A., 1996, “Methodological Naturalism?”, in J. van der Meer (ed.), Facets of Faith and Science, Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
- Price, H., 2011, Naturalism without Mirrors, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Pust, J., 2014, “Intuition”, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/intuition/>.
- Putnam, H., 1971, Philosophy of Logic, New York: Harper.
- Ridge, M., 2014, “Moral Non-Naturalism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/moral-non-naturalism/>.
- Robb, D. and J. Heil, 2014, “Mental Causation”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/mental-causation/>.
- Rosen, G., 1990, “Modal Fictionalism”, Mind, 99: 327–54.
- Russell, B., 1917, “On Scientific Method in Philosophy”, in his Mysticism and Logic, London: Longmans.
- Russell, G., 2008, Truth in Virtue of Meaning, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Shafer-Landau, R., 2003, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Shapiro, S., 2000, “Frege Meets Dedekind: A Neologicist Treatment of Real Analysis”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 41: 335–64.
- Smart, J.J.C., 1959, “Sensations and Brain Processes”, Philosophical Review, 68: 141–56.
- Sosa, E., 1998, “Minimal Intuition”, in DePaul and Ramsey 1998: 257–70.
- –––, 2007, “Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Intuition”, Philosophical Studies, 132: 99–107.
- Spurrett, D. and Papineau, D., 1999, “A Note on the Completeness of ‘Physics’”, Analysis, 59: 25–29.
- Steward, H., 2012, A Metaphysics for Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Strevens, M., 2019, Thinking Off Your Feet, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- Stoljar, D., 2015, “Physicalism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/physicalism/>.
- Sturgeon, N., 1985, “Moral Explanations”, in D. Copp and D. Zimmerman (eds.), Morality, Reason, and Truth, Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman and Allanheld, 49–78.
- Turner, F., 1974, Between Science and Religion. The Reaction to Scientific Naturalism in Late Victorian England, New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Wedgwood, R., 2007, The Nature of Normativity, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Weinberg, J., S. Nichols, and S. Stich, 2001, “Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions”, Philosophical Topics, 29: 429–460.
- Wilson, J., 2006, “On Characterizing the Mental”, Philosophical Studies, 131: 61–99.
- Williamson, T., 2007, The Philosophy of Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell.
- –––, 2011, “Philosophical Expertise and the Burden of Proof”, Metaphilosophy, 42(2): 215–29.
- –––, 2013, “How Deep is the Distinction between A Priori and A Posteriori Knowledge?”, in A. Casullo and J. Thurow (eds.), The A Priori in Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 291–312.
- Woodward, J., 2005, Making Things Happen, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Woolhouse, R., 1985, “Leibniz’s Reaction to Cartesian Interaction”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 86: 69–82.
- Wright, C., 1983, Frege’s Conception of Numbers as Objects, Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.
- –––, 1992, Truth and Objectivity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- –––, 2000, “Neo-Fregean Foundations for Real Analysis: Some Reflections on Frege’s Constraint”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 41: 317–34.
- Yablo, S., 1992, “Mental Causation”, Philosophical Review, 101: 245–280.
- Yalowitz, S., 2014, “Anomalous Monism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/anomalous-monism/>.